What makes a theory scientific?
This post has been reblogged from Farnam Street.This site is run by Shane Parrish a young Canadian who says that his goal is to " help you go to bed each night smarter than when you woke up. I’ll do this by giving you tools, ideas, and frameworks for thinking." I subscribe to the feed from his site. I liked this post and thought it might interest some of you who are not familiar with Shane's writings. I have changed the heading of the post however.
You can read the original post here.
What makes a theory scientific?
It’s not immediately clear, to the layman, what the
essential difference is between science and something masquerading as science:
pseudoscience. The distinction gets at the core of what comprises human
knowledge: How do we actually know something to be true? Is it simply because
our powers of observation tell us so? Or is there more to it?
Sir Karl Popper, the scientific philosopher, was interested
in the same problem. How do we actually define the scientific process? How do
we know which theories can be said to be truly explanatory?
He began addressing it in a lecture, which is printed in the
book Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge :
When I received the list of participants in this course and
realized that I had been asked to speak to philosophical colleagues I thought,
after some hesitation and consultation, that you would probably prefer me to
speak about those problems which interest me most, and about those developments
with which I am most intimately acquainted. I therefore decided to do what I
have never done before: to give you a report on my own work in the philosophy
of science, since the autumn of 1919 when I first began to grapple with the
problem, ‘When should a theory be ranked as scientific?’ or ‘Is there a
criterion for the scientific character or status of a theory?’
Popper saw a problem with the number of theories he
considered non-scientific that, on their surface, seemed to have a lot in
common with good, hard, rigorous science. But the question of how we decide
which theories are compatible with the scientific method, and those which are
not, was harder than it seemed.
***
It is most common to say that science is done by collecting
observations and grinding out theories from them. Charles Darwin once said,
after working long and hard at the problem of the Origin of Species,
“My mind seems to have become a kind of machine for grinding
general laws out of large collections of facts.”
This is a popularly accepted notion. We observe, observe,
and observe, and we look for theories to best explain the mass of facts.
(Although even this is not really true: Popper points out that we must start
with some a priori knowledge to be able to generate new knowledge. Observation
is always done with some hypotheses in mind–we can’t understand the world from
a totally blank slate.
The problem, as Popper saw it, is that some bodies of
knowledge more properly named pseudosciences would be considered scientific if
the “Observe & Deduce” operating definition were left alone. For example, a
believing astrologist can ably provide you with “evidence” that their theories
are sound. The biographical information of a great many people can be explained
this way, they’d say.
The astrologist would tell you, for example, about how
“Leos” seek to be the center of attention; ambitious, strong, seeking
limelight. As proof, they might follow up with a host of real-life Leos:
World-leaders, celebrities, politicians, and so on. In some sense, the theory
would hold up. The observations could be explained by the theory, which is how
science works, right?
Sir Karl ran into this problem in a concrete way because he
lived during a time when psychoanalytic theories were all the rage at just the
same time Einstein was laying out a new foundation for the physical sciences
with the concept of relativity. What made Popper uncomfortable were comparisons
between the two. Why did he feel so uneasy putting Marxist theories and
Freudian psychology in the same category of knowledge as Einstein’s Relativity?
Did all three not have vast explanatory power in the world? Each theory’s
proponents certainly believed so, but Popper was not satisfied.
“It was during the summer of 1919 that I began to feel more
and more dissatisfied with these three theories–the Marxist theory of history,
psychoanalysis, and individual psychology; and I began to feel dubious about
their claims to scientific status. My problem perhaps first took the simple
form, ‘What is wrong with Marxism, psycho-analysis, and individual psychology?
Why are they so different from physical theories, from Newton’s theory, and
especially from the theory of relativity?’
I found that those of my friends who were admirers of Marx,
Freud, and Adler, were impressed by a number of points common to these
theories, and especially by their apparent explanatory power. These theories
appeared to be able to explain practically everything that happened within the
fields to which they referred. The study of any of them seemed to have the
effect of an intellectual conversion or revelation, opening your eyes to a new
truth hidden from those not yet initiated. Once your eyes were thus opened you
saw confirming instances everywhere: the world was full of verifications of the
theory.
Whatever happened always confirmed it. Thus its truth
appeared manifest; and unbelievers were clearly people who did not want to see
the manifest truth; who refused to see it, either because it was against their
class interest, or because of their repressions which were still ‘un-analysed’
and crying aloud for treatment.”
Here was the salient problem: The proponents of these new
sciences saw validations and verifications of their theories everywhere. If you
were having trouble as an adult, it could always be explained by something your
mother or father had done to you when you were young, some repressed
something-or-other that hadn’t been analyzed and solved. They were confirmation
bias machines.
What was the missing element? Popper had figured it out
before long: The non-scientific theories could not be falsified. They were not
testable in a legitimate way. There was no possible objection that could be
raised which would show the theory to be wrong.
In a true science, the following statement can be easily made:
“If x happens, it would show demonstrably that theory y is not true.” We can
then design an experiment, a physical one or sometimes a simple thought
experiment, to figure out if x actually does happen. It’s the opposite of looking for
verification; you must try to show the theory is incorrect, and if you fail to
do so, thereby strengthen it.
Pseudosciences cannot and do not do this–they are not strong
enough to hold up. As an example, Popper discussed Freud’s theories of the mind
in relation to Alfred Adler’s so-called “individual psychology,” which was
popular at the time:
I may illustrate this by two very different examples of
human behaviour: that of a man who pushes a child into the water with the
intention of drowning it; and that of a man who sacrifices his life in an
attempt to save the child. Each of these two cases can be explained with equal
ease in Freudian and in Adlerian terms. According to Freud the first man
suffered from repression (say, of some component of his Oedipus complex), while
the second man had achieved sublimation. According to Adler the first man
suffered from feelings of inferiority (producing perhaps the need to prove to
himself that he dared to commit some crime), and so did the second man (whose
need was to prove to himself that he dared to rescue the child). I could not
think of any human behaviour which could not be interpreted in terms of either
theory. It was precisely this fact–that they always fitted, that they were
always confirmed–which in the eyes of their admirers constituted the strongest
argument in favour of these theories. It began to dawn on me that this apparent
strength was in fact their weakness.
Popper contrasted these theories against Relativity, which
made specific, verifiable predictions, giving the conditions under which the
predictions could be shown false. It turned out that Einstein’s predictions
came to be true when tested, thus verifying the theory through attempts to
falsify it. But the essential nature of the theory gave grounds under which it
could have been wrong. To this day, physicists seek to figure out where
Relativity breaks down in order to come to a more fundamental understanding of
physical reality. And while the theory may eventually be proven incomplete or a
special case of a more general phenomenon, it has still made accurate, testable
predictions that have led to practical breakthroughs.
Thus, in Popper’s words, science requires testability: “If
observation shows that the predicted effect is definitely absent, then the
theory is simply refuted.” This means a
good theory must have an element of risk to it. It must be able to be proven
wrong under stated conditions.
From there, Popper laid out his essential conclusions, which
are useful to any thinker trying to figure out if a theory they hold dear is
something that can be put in the scientific realm:
1. It is easy to obtain confirmations, or verifications, for
nearly every theory–if we look for confirmations.
2. Confirmations should count only if they are the result of
risky predictions; that is to say, if, unenlightened by the theory in question,
we should have expected an event which was incompatible with the theory–an
event which would have refuted the theory.
3. Every ‘good’ scientific theory is a prohibition: it
forbids certain things to happen. The more a theory forbids, the better it is.
4. A theory which is not refutable by any conceivable event
is nonscientific. Irrefutability is not a virtue of a theory (as people often
think) but a vice.
5. Every genuine test of a theory is an attempt to falsify
it, or to refute it. Testability is falsifiability; but there are degrees of
testability: some theories are more testable, more exposed to refutation, than
others; they take, as it were, greater risks.
6. Confirming evidence should not count except when it is
the result of a genuine test of the theory; and this means that it can be
presented as a serious but unsuccessful attempt to falsify the theory. (I now
speak in such cases of ‘corroborating evidence’.)
7. Some genuinely testable theories, when found to be false,
are still upheld by their admirers–for example by introducing ad hoc some
auxiliary assumption, or by re-interpreting the theory ad hoc in such a way
that it escapes refutation. Such a procedure is always possible, but it rescues
the theory from refutation only at the price of destroying, or at least
lowering, its scientific status. (I later described such a rescuing operation
as a ‘conventionalist twist’ or a ‘conventionalist stratagem’.)
One can sum up all this by saying that the criterion of the
scientific status of a theory is its falsifiability, or refutability, or
testability.
Finally, Popper was careful to say that it is not possible
to prove that Freudianism was not true, at least in part. But we can say that
we simply don’t know whether it’s true, because it does not make specific
testable predictions. It may have many kernels of truth in it, but we can’t
tell. The theory would have to be restated.
This is the essential “line of demarcation,“ as Popper
called it, between science and pseudoscience.
Comments